Political representation
Part of the Politics series |
Democracy |
---|
Politics portal |
Political representation is the activity of making citizens "present" in public policy-making processes when political actors act in the best interest of citizens according to Hanna Pitkin's Concept of Representation (1967).[1][2]
This definition of political representation is consistent with a wide variety of views on what representing implies and what the duties of representatives are.[3] For example, representing may imply acting on the expressed wishes of citizens, but it may alternatively imply acting according to what the representatives themselves judge is in the best interests of citizens.[3]
And representatives may be viewed as individuals who have been authorized to act on the behalf of others, or may alternatively be viewed as those who will be held to account by those they are representing.[2] Political representation can happen along different units such as social groups and area, and there are different types of representation such as substantive representation and descriptive representation.[2]
Views of political representation
[edit]Under the accountability view, a representative is an individual who will be held to account.[4] Representatives are held accountable if citizens can judge whether the representative is acting in their best interest and sanction the representative accordingly.[3] The descriptive and symbolic views of political representation describe the ways in which political representatives "stand for" the people they represent.[2] Descriptive representatives "stand for" to the extent that they resemble, in their descriptive characteristics (e.g. race, gender, class etc.), the people they represent.[5] On the other hand, symbolic representatives "stand for" the people they represent as long as those people believe in or accept them as their representative.[6] Hanna Fenichel Pitkin argues that these views of political representation give an inadequate account of political representation because they lack an account both of how representatives "act for" the represented and the normative criteria for judging representative's actions. Hence, Pitkin proposes a substantive view of representation. In this view of political representation, representation is defined as substantive "acting for", by representatives, the interests of the people they represent.[6]
In contrast, Jane Mansbridge has identified four views of democratic political representation: promissory, anticipatory, surrogate and gyroscopic. Mansbridge argues that each of these views provides an account of both how democratic political representatives "act for" the people they represent and the normative criteria for assessing the actions of representatives.[7] Promissory representation is a form of representation in which representatives are chosen and assessed based on the promises they make to the people they represent during election campaigns. For Mansbridge, promissory representation, preoccupied with how representatives are chosen (authorized) and held to account through elections, is the traditional view of democratic political representation. Anticipatory, surrogate and gyroscopic representation, on the other hand, are more modern views that have emerged from the work of empirical political scientists. Anticipatory representatives take actions that they believe voters (the represented) will reward in the next election. Surrogate representation occurs when representatives "act for" the interest of people outside their constituencies. Finally, in gyroscopic representation, representatives use their own judgements to determine how and for what they should act for on behalf of the people they represent.[1]
Under Andrew Rehfeld's general theory of representation, a person is considered a representative as long as the particular group they represent judges them as such.[8] In any case of political representation, there are representatives, the represented, a selection agent, a relevant audience and rules by which the relevant judge whether a person is a representative.[8] Representatives are those who are selected by a selection agent from a larger set of qualified individuals who are then judged to representatives by a relevant audience using particular rules of judgement. The rules by which a relevant audience judges whether a person is a representative can be either democratic or non-democratic. In a case where the selection agent, relevant audience and the represented are the same and the rules of judgment are democratic (e.g. elections), the familiar democratic case of political representation arises and where they are not, undemocratic cases arise.
Units of representation
[edit]Representation by population
[edit]This is the preferred (and far more common) method for democratic countries, where elected representatives will be chosen by similarly-sized groups of voters. The shortened term "rep-by-pop" is used in Canada[9][10] whereas "one person, one vote" is more common in the U.S.[11][12]
Representation by area
[edit]This form of representation tends to occur as a political necessity for unifying many independent actors, such as in a federation (e.g. NATO, the UN). It's highly unusual (and controversial) where it exists within countries because of its violation of the 'one person, one vote' principle. Examples of representation by area within countries tend to be historical remnants of when those countries were federations before their unification. For example, the American Constitution was not quite able to eliminate its rep-by-area features due to smaller states already holding disproportionate power in the proceedings from the Articles of Confederation. In Canada, provinces such as Prince Edward Island also have unequal representation in Parliament (in the Commons as well as the Senate) relative to Ontario, British Columbia, and Alberta, largely for similar historical reasons.
Models of representation
[edit]Models of representation refer to ways in which elected officials behave in representative democracies. There are three main types: delegate, trustee, and politico.[citation needed]
Delegate model
[edit]A delegate is someone who is elected to represent and convey the views of others. The delegate model of representation suggests that representatives have little or no capacity to exercise their own judgement or preferences. They are merely elected to be the mouthpiece of their constituency and act only the way their constituents would want them to, regardless of their own opinion.
Joseph Tussman stated, "The essence of representation is the delegation or granting of authority. To authorize a representative is to grant another the right to act for oneself. Within the limits of the grant of authority one is, in fact, committing himself in advance to the decision or will of another".[13]
Trustee model
[edit]A trustee is someone who acts on behalf of others, using their knowledge, experience and intelligence upon a certain field. The trustee model contrasts with the delegate model as this time constituents "entrust" their elected representatives to represent them however they see fit, with autonomy to vote and behave in the best way for their constituents.
Edmund Burke, who formulated the model, stated in a speech, "You choose a member indeed; but when you have chosen him he is not member of Bristol, but he is a member of parliament...your representative owes you, not his industry only, but his judgement; and he betrays, instead of serving you, if he sacrifices it to your own opinion".[14]
Politico model
[edit]The politico model came about when theorists recognized that representatives rarely consistently act as just a delegate or just a trustee when representing their constituents. It is a hybrid of the two models discussed above and involves representatives acting as delegates and trustees, depending on the issue.[citation needed]
Other models
[edit]The mandate model views representatives as less independent actors. This came about after the emergence of modern political parties; now constituents rarely vote for a representative based on their personal qualities but more broadly, they vote for their party to be elected into government. A mandate is an order or instruction from a superior body therefore this model suggests representatives follow the party line and must carry out policies outlined during election campaigns.[15]
The resemblance model is less concerned about the way representatives are selected and more concerned whether they resemble the group they claim to represent. It is similar to descriptive representation, they argue that to represent a group of people such as the working class or women to its full potential you must be part of that social group yourself. Therefore, only people who have shared experiences and interests can fully identify with particular issues.[16]
Types of representation
[edit]An alternative way of considering types of representation is as follows:
Substantive representation
[edit]Substantive representation occurs when representatives' opinions and actions reflect the wishes, needs, and interests of the people they represent.[17] Democratic theorists often study substantive representation in terms of ideological congruence, meaning that representation is high when representatives hold the same policy positions as their constituents.[18] Recent research shows that the ideological opinion-policy relationship is upheld for both foreign and domestic affairs, although foreign affairs and defense policy were long considered immune to public pressure.[19] According to Hanna F. Pitkin's The Concept of Representation (1967), the standard for assessing the quality of substantive representation is the representative's responsiveness to the evolving needs of their citizenry.[20] As a result, low substantive representation in representative democracies usually arises from representatives' inability to judge and act on the interests of the public rather than inactivity in office.[21] Pitkin also argues that substantive representation should be apparent through the nature of government action between elections.[22] Thus, substantive representation is predicated on the fact that democracy is evident between elections rather than isolated to formal procedures like voting.[23]
Recently, Pitkin's concept of substantive representation has been criticized by several political scientists on the grounds that it "assumes a static notion that interests are entities waiting to be brought into the representational process."[24] Among these scholars is Michael Saward (2010), who argues that substantive representation should be constructed as a process of "claims-making" in which representatives "speak for" their constituents.[25] However, Ellie Severs (2012) disparages this logic, as she claims it obscures the interactions between representatives and the represented that are essential to the substantive representation process.[26]
Substantive representation is not a universally accepted concept; minimalist theorists like Adam Przeworski (1999) reject the idea that representatives can be driven to act in the best interests of the public.[27] In contrast to substantive representation, minimalists believe that democracy is merely a system in which competitive elections select rulers and that democracies should be defended regardless of the outcomes they produce for their citizenry.[28] Nonetheless, democratic theorists often consider substantive representation to be salient due to its emphasis on action in office, particularly in relation to the interests of women and ethnic minorities.[18]
Descriptive representation
[edit]Scholars have defined representation as "the making present in some sense of something which is nevertheless not present literally or in fact".[29] Descriptive representation is the idea that a group elects an individual to represent them who in their own characteristics mirror some of the more frequent experiences and outward manifestations of the group.[30] This descriptive representation can have again different types such as "perfect over representation", "over representation", "proper representation", "under/nominal representation" & "No representation".[31] In this form of representation, representatives are in their own persons and lives in some sense typical of the larger class of persons whom they represent.[32] For example, certain ethnic groups or gender-based groups may want to elect a leader that shares these descriptive characteristics as they may be politically relevant. Disadvantaged groups may gain benefit from descriptive representation primarily in two ways:
- When there is mistrust: This refers to a situation where communication between the group and its representatives has been inadequate.[30] In these cases, descriptive representation promotes vertical communication between representatives and their group of constituents.[30]
- When interests are uncrystallized: In certain historical moments, citizen interests are not clearly defined. Either the issues have not been on the political agenda for long, or candidates have not taken public positions on them.[30] In this case, the best way to have one's substantive interests represented is often to choose a descriptive representative whose characteristics match one's own.[32]
Descriptive representation can be instituted by political parties independently where they set aside a certain number of party seats for particular groups.[33] It can also be instituted through national electoral quotas either by reserving seats for office or candidate quotas for political parties.[33]
Traditionally, quotas have been thought of as a way of providing adequate representation for previously disadvantaged groups such as women or oppressed ethnic groups.[30] However, another way of conceptualizing quotas is to institute a maximum or ceiling quota for advantaged groups.[34] This may improve the meritocracy of the system and improve the process of candidate selection[34]
Empirically, quotas show mixed results. In Lesotho, quota-mandated female representation has had no effect or even reduced several dimensions of women's engagement with local politics.[35] In Argentina, quotas have mandated negative stereotypes about women politicians.[36] Meanwhile, in India, women are more likely to win an election in a constituency that formerly had quotas, even when the quotas are removed,[37] and women leaders provide public goods favoured by women constituents.[38] Evidence also shows that while caste-based quotas may not change stereotypes of how people view the oppressed caste group, they do change the social norms of interaction between caste groups[39][note 1]
Dyadic representation
[edit]Dyadic representation refers to the degree to which and ways by which elected legislators represent the preferences or interests of the specific geographic constituencies from which they are elected. Candidates who run for legislative office in an individual constituency or as a member of a list of party candidates are especially motivated to provide dyadic representation. As Carey and Shugart (1995, 417) observe, they have "incentives to cultivate a personal vote" beyond whatever support their party label will produce. Personal vote seeking might arise from representing the public policy interests of the constituency (by way of either the delegate, responsible party, or trustee models noted above), providing it "pork barrel" goods, offering service to individual constituents as by helping them acquire government services, and symbolic actions.
The most abundant scientific scholarship on dyadic representation has been for the U.S. Congress and for policy representation of constituencies by the members of the Congress. Miller and Stokes (1963) presented the seminal research of this kind in an exploratory effort to account for when alternative models of policy representation arise. Their work has been emulated, replicated, and enlarged by a host of subsequent studies. The most advanced theoretical formulation in this body of work, however, is by Hurley and Hill (2003) and by Hill, Jordan, and Hurley (2015) who present a theory that accounts well for when belief sharing representation, delegate representation, trustee representation, responsible party representation, and party elite led representation will arise.
Collective representation
[edit]The concept of collective representation can be found in various normative theory and scientific works, but Weissberg (1978, 535) offered the first systematic characterization of it in the scientific literature and for the U.S. Congress, defining such representation as "Whether Congress as an institution represents the American people, not whether each member of Congress represented his or her particular district." Hurley (1982) elaborated and qualified Weissberg's explication of how such representation should be assessed and how it relates to dyadic representation. Stimson, MacKuen, and Erikson (1995), offer the most advanced theoretical exposition of such representation for the U.S. Congress. And the latter work was extended in Erikson, MacKuen, and Stimson (2002).
In most parliamentary political systems with strong (or ideologically unified) political parties and where the election system is dominated by parties instead of individual candidates, the primary basis for representation is also a collective, party based one. The foundational work on assessing such representation is that of Huber and Powell (1994) and Powell (2000).
See also
[edit]- Apportionment and redistricting
- Delegate vs trustee model of representation
- Gerrymandering
- Interactive representation
- Proportional Representation
- Representative democracy
- Sortition
- Taxation without representation
Notes
[edit]- ^ For data on gender quota adoption from 1947 to 2015, see the Quota Adoption and Reform Over Time (QAROT) data set.
References
[edit]- ^ a b Dovi, Suzanne (2018). Political Representation. The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Winter 2017 Edition). Retrieved 19 November 2019.
- ^ a b c d Pitkin, Hanna Fenichel (1967). The concept of representation. Berkeley. ISBN 0520021568. OCLC 498382.
{{cite book}}
: CS1 maint: location missing publisher (link) - ^ a b c Democracy, accountability, and representation. Przeworski, Adam., Stokes, Susan Carol., Manin, Bernard. Cambridge, U.K.: Cambridge University Press. 1999. ISBN 9781139175104. OCLC 817932765.
{{cite book}}
: CS1 maint: others (link) - ^ Pitkin, Hanna (1967). The Concept of Representation. Berkeley and Los Angeles: University of California Press. pp. 38–39, 55. ISBN 978-0520021563.
- ^ Pitkin, Hanna (1967). The Concept of Representation. Berkeley and Los Angeles: University of California Press. p. 63. ISBN 978-0520021563.
- ^ a b Pitkin, Hanna (1967). The Concept of Representation. Berkeley and Los Angeles: University of California Press. p. 174. ISBN 978-0520021563.
- ^ Mansbridge, Jane (Nov 2003). "Rethinking Representation". The American Political Science Review. 97 (4): 515–528. doi:10.1017/S0003055403000856. JSTOR 359302. S2CID 210059562.
- ^ a b Rehfeld, Andrew (2006). "Toward a General Theory of Political Representation". The Journal of Politics. 68: 1–21. CiteSeerX 10.1.1.528.5810. doi:10.1111/j.1468-2508.2006.00365.x. S2CID 96451393.
- ^ "rep by pop". Oxford English Dictionary. Oxford University Press. Retrieved 7 November 2023.
- ^ "Rep by Pop". The Canadian Encyclopedia. Anthony Wilson-Smith. 12 December 2019.
- ^ "One Person, One Vote". The Constitution Project. the documentary group. 2017. Retrieved 7 November 2023.
- ^ Text of Gray v. Sanders, 372 U.S. 368 (1963) is available from: Findlaw Justia Library of Congress Oyez (oral argument audio)
- ^ Tussman, Joseph (1947). The Political Theory of Thomas Hobbes. Unpul. diss. p. 117.
- ^ "Representation: Edmund Burke, Speech to the Electors of Bristol". press-pubs.uchicago.edu. Retrieved 2018-12-07.
- ^ Heywood, Andrew (2013). Politics. New York: PALGRAVE MACMILLAN. p. 200.
- ^ Heywood, Andrew (2013). Politics. New York: PALGRAVE MACMILLAN. pp. 201–202.
- ^ [Arnesen, Sveinung, and Yvette Peters. “The Legitimacy of Representation: How Descriptive, Formal, and Responsiveness Representation Affect the Acceptability of Political Decisions.” Comparative Political Studies 51, no. 7 (2017): 873. https://doi.org/10.1177/0010414017720702.]
- ^ a b [Clark, William Roberts, Matt Golder, and Sona Nadenichek Golder. “Chapter 14: Consequences of Democratic Institutions.” Essay. In Foundations of Comparative Politics, 357. Thousand Oaks, CA: CQ Press, 2019.]
- ^ [Jacobs, Lawrence R., and Robert Y. Shapiro. “Studying Substantive Democracy.” PS: Political Science and Politics 27, no. 1 (March 1994): 10. https://doi.org/10.2307/420450.]
- ^ [Celis, Karen. “On Substantive Representation, Diversity, and Responsiveness.” Cambridge University Press 8, no. 4 (December 12, 2012): 525. https://doi.org/10.1017/S1743923X12000542.]
- ^ [ Kuper, Andrew. “Representation as Responsiveness.” Essay. In Democracy beyond Borders: Justice and Representation in Global Institutions, 77. Oxford: Oxford Univ. Press, 2004.]
- ^ [Jacobs, Lawrence R., and Robert Y. Shapiro. “Studying Substantive Democracy.” PS: Political Science and Politics 27, no. 1 (March 1994): 11. https://doi.org/10.2307/420450.]
- ^ [ Jacobs, Lawrence R., and Robert Y. Shapiro. “Studying Substantive Democracy.” PS: Political Science and Politics 27, no. 1 (March 1994): 11. https://doi.org/10.2307/420450.]
- ^ [Celis, Karen. “On Substantive Representation, Diversity, and Responsiveness.” Cambridge University Press 8, no. 4 (December 12, 2012): 527. https://doi.org/10.1017/S1743923X12000542.]
- ^ [Severs, Eline. “Substantive Representation through a Claims-Making Lens: A Strategy for the Identification and Analysis of Substantive Claims.” Representation 48, no. 2 (2012): 171. https://doi.org/10.1080/00344893.2012.683491.]
- ^ [Severs, Eline. “Substantive Representation through a Claims-Making Lens: A Strategy for the Identification and Analysis of Substantive Claims.” Representation 48, no. 2 (2012): 178. https://doi.org/10.1080/00344893.2012.683491.]
- ^ [Kuper, Andrew. “Representation as Responsiveness.” Essay. In Democracy beyond Borders: Justice and Representation in Global Institutions, 98. Oxford: Oxford Univ. Press, 2004.]
- ^ [Shapiro, Ian, Casiano Hacker-Cordón, and Adam Przeworski . “Minimalist Conception of Democracy: A Defense.” Essay. In Democracy's Value, 12–17. Cambridge etc.: Cambridge University Press, 2005.]
- ^ Pitkin, Hanna (1967). The Concept of Representation. Berkeley and Los Angeles: University of California Press. p. 8.
- ^ a b c d e Mansbridge, Jane (1999). "Should Blacks Represent Blacks and Women Represent Women? A Contingent "Yes"". The Journal of Politics. 61 (3): 628–657. doi:10.2307/2647821. ISSN 0022-3816. JSTOR 2647821. S2CID 37133536.
- ^ Baniamin, Hasan Muhammad; Jamil, Ishtiaq (2021-06-13). "Effects of representative bureaucracy on perceived performance and fairness: Experimental evidence from South Asia". Public Administration. 101: 284–302. doi:10.1111/padm.12758. S2CID 236301887.
- ^ a b Phillips, Anne (1995). The Politics of Presence. Oxford: Clarendon Press. ISBN 0-19-827942-6.
- ^ a b Hughes, Melanie; Paxton, Pamela; Clayton, Amanda; Zetterberg, Par (2019). "Global gender quota adoption, implementation and reform". Comparative Politics. 51 (2): 219–238. doi:10.5129/001041519X15647434969795. PMC 10978000. PMID 38549789.
- ^ a b Murray, Rainbow (2014). "Quotas for Men: Reframing Gender Quotas as a Means of Improving Representation for All". The American Political Science Review. 108 (3): 520–532. doi:10.1017/S0003055414000239. ISSN 0003-0554. JSTOR 43654390.
- ^ Clayton, Amanda (2015). "Women's Political Engagement Under Quota-Mandated Female Representation: Evidence From a Randomized Policy Experiment". Comparative Political Studies. 48 (3): 333–369. doi:10.1177/0010414014548104. ISSN 0010-4140. S2CID 20079395.
- ^ Franceschet, Susan; Piscopo, Jennifer M. (2008). "Gender Quotas and Women's Substantive Representation: Lessons from Argentina". Politics & Gender. 4 (3). doi:10.1017/S1743923X08000342. ISSN 1743-923X. S2CID 67759059.
- ^ Bhavnani, Rikhil R. (2009). "Do Electoral Quotas Work after They Are Withdrawn? Evidence from a Natural Experiment in India". American Political Science Review. 103 (1): 23–35. doi:10.1017/S0003055409090029. ISSN 0003-0554. S2CID 229169083.
- ^ Chattopadhyay, Raghabendra; Duflo, Esther (2004-09-01). "Women as Policy Makers: Evidence from a Randomized Policy Experiment in India" (PDF). Econometrica. 72 (5): 1409–1443. doi:10.1111/j.1468-0262.2004.00539.x. hdl:1721.1/39126. ISSN 1468-0262.
- ^ Chauchard, Simon (2014). "Can Descriptive Representation Change Beliefs about a Stigmatized Group? Evidence from Rural India". The American Political Science Review. 108 (2): 403–422. doi:10.1017/S0003055414000033. ISSN 0003-0554. JSTOR 43654380. S2CID 59025621.
Bibliography
[edit]- Carey, John M. and Matthew Soberg Shugart. (1995) "Incentives to Cultivate a Personal Vote: A Rank Ordering of Electoral Formulas." Electoral Studies vol 14(4): 417–439.
- Cerutti, Carlo (2017) "La rappresentanza politica nei gruppi del Parlamento europeo. Il divieto di mandato imperativo", Wolters Kluwer-CEDAM, Milano.
- Disch, Lisa. (2011) "Toward a Mobilization Conception of Democratic Representation" American Political Science Review, vol. 105(1): 100–114.
- Erikson, Robert S., Michael B. MacKuen, and James A. Stimson. (2002)The Macro Polity Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
- Huber, John D. and G. Bingham Powell, Jr. (1994) "Congruence Between Citizens and Policymakers in Two Visions of Liberal Democracy" World Politics vol. 46(April): 291–326.
- Hill, Kim Quaile, Soren Jordan, and Patricia A. Hurley (2015) Representation in Congress: A Unified Theory. Cambridge University Press.
- Hurley, Patricia A. (1982) "Collective Representation Reappraised" Legislative Studies Quarterly vol. VII(February): 119–136.
- Hurley, Patricia A. and Kim Quaile Hill. (2003) "Beyond the Demand-Input Model: A Theory of Representational Linkages." Journal of Politics vol.65(May): 304–326.
- Mansbridge, Jane. (1999) "Should Blacks Represent Blacks and Women Represent Women? A Contingent `Yes'" Journal of Politics, vol. 61(3): 627–657.
- Miller, Warren E. and Donald E. Stokes. (1963) "Constituency Influence in Congress." American Political Science Review vol. 57(March): 45–56.
- Phillips, Anne. (1995) The Politics of Presence. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
- Pitkin, Hanna. (1967) The Concept of Representation. University of California Press.
- Plotke, David. (1997) "Representation is Democracy." Constellations 4 (1): 19–34.
- Powell, G. Bingham, Jr. (2000) Elections as Instruments of Democracy New Haven, CT: Yale University Press.
- Stimson, James A., Michael B. MacKuen, and Robert S. Erikson. (1995) "Dynamic Representation" American Political Science Review vol. 89(September): 543–565.
- Ulbig, Stacy G. (2005) "Political Realities and Political Trust: Descriptive Representation in Municipal Government". Southwestern Political Science Association Meeting. Retrieved from [1] on July 19, 2005.
- Vieira, Mónica Brito and David Runciman. (2008) Representation. Cambridge: Polity Press.
- Weissberg, Robert. (1978) "Collective vs. Dyadic Representation in Congress." American Political Science Review vol. 72(June): 535–547.
- Williams, Melissa S. (1998) Voice, Trust, and Memory: Marginalized Groups and the Failings of Liberal Representation. Princeton: Princeton University Press.
External links
[edit]- Analysis of reapportionment after the 1990 US census, from an Arizona State University website
- Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy entry on Political Representation by Suzanne Dovi. http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/political-representation/
- Chisholm, Hugh (1911). . Encyclopædia Britannica. Vol. 23 (11th ed.). pp. 108–116.